Among the many
ideas developed in H.L.A. Hart’s famous and enduring work, ‘The Concept of Law’
is ‘the distinction between primary and secondary legal rules, where a primary
rule governs conduct and a secondary rule allows of the creation, alteration,
or extinction of primary rules’. The primary rules are obligation which imposes
duties, and giving liberties to individuals (apply directly to the citizens).
They represent standard modes of behaviour that obligate the members of society
to perform or abstain from certain types of actions. These rules restrict
violence, theft and deception.
Meanwhile,
secondary rules are “rules about rules”; they regulate how other rules are
made, changed, applied and enforced. They establish official machinery for the
recognition and enforcement of primary rules. Hart illustrates the need for
secondary rules in a complex legal system by imagining a society run only with
primary rules. He calls these ‘primitive legal systems’ and thinks they
constitute a borderline legal system. Also, according to his theory, there are
several types of secondary rules such as “rule/rules of recognition”, “rules of
change”, “rules of adjudication”, and “rules of sanction”.
The “rule/rules
of recognition” can counter the ‘uncertainty’ of traditional law (these rules
delineate what is and what is not a legal rule). Law is only valid once it goes
through “rule/rules of recognition”. For example, in Malaysia, the law will
become valid when it goes through the first reading until the executive
signing). In Cuba, the law will get validity after pronouncement from the
dictator that recognized the law.
The “rules of
change” specify how legal rules can be amended or repealed. They keep society
dynamic and counter the ‘static nature’ of the traditional law. For example, in
Malaysia, Article 159 of the Federal Constitution contains power of simple
majority to amend ordinary law and two-third majority to change constitution.
The system must have some mechanism or method to complement all these changes.
In addition,
developed legal systems have “rules of adjudication” to counter the
‘inefficiency’ in the traditional law (these rules say how disputes are
resolved and legal rules enforced). Hart thinks that the system of sanctions is
needed to ensure human obey the law. The “rules of sanction” impose punishment
on wrongdoers to ensure non-repetition of the crime.
By way of
criticism, it must be noted that many jurists (among them Fuller and Lloyd)
have hammered home the point that the strict division of rules into primary and
secondary cannot be maintained. The same rule, such as the rule of judicial
precedent, may create a power plus a duty. Lloyd argues that Hart ignored the
institutional framework within which rules operate. Hart’s reply is that a
rule-based theory of law encompasses institutions. Hart is not entirely
correct. Many important institutions like the cabinet in United Kingdom (UK)
and the Public Complaints Bureau in Malaysia exist extra-legally.
In contrast
with Hart’s theory, Webber provides an institutional view of the continuity of
law as opposed to Hart’s internal point of view. Hart downplayed the role of
force and sanction in legal system by replacing the imperative theory with his
idea of the internal point of view. The idea that rules work not because of
sanctions (and the attendant element of fear) but because of “acceptance” of
these rules by citizens and officials opens up vast new vistas of ethics,
sociology, psychology and anthropology in order to explore “why” and “why not”
citizens and officials show fidelity to the rules of the system. Sadly, Hart
did not venture into these areas to any appreciable extent.
Fitzgerald says
that the significance of secondary rules has been exaggerated by Hart. The
secondary rules may be altered without creating an entirely new legal system
such as the passage of the Parliament Act 1911 in the UK and the 1984 amendment
to Article 66 of Federal Constitution in Malaysia to redefine the concept of
Parliament. It should be noted that, in ‘The Concept of Law’, H.L.A Hart does
not demonstrate what his notion of a primitive or pre-legal system actually
looks like, or how it functions. Hart’s theory of law as the union of primary
and secondary rules can be useful as a means of analysis, but his notion of the
primitive system is perhaps fatally flawed and may be superfluous.
Hart’s
“rule/rules of recognition” is definitely not free from criticism.
Subsequently, Joseph Raz, John Finnis, Neil MacCormick, Jules Coleman, Jeremy
Waldron, John Gardner and many others did have their own view in identifying
what is the law in the classical tradition than other analytical philosophers
did before Hart. Joseph Raz argues whether the “rule/rules of recognition” is
best understood as a duty-imposing or power-conferring rule; and whether there
can be more than one “rule/rules of recognition” within a given legal system.
Meanwhile, John Finnis criticise that Hart leaves insufficiently specified the
sort of attitude towards the “rule/rules of recognition” that the officials
have. Finnis tried to establish a complex variant of natural law in that the
central set of elements constituting an official’s acceptance of a “rule/rules
of recognition” is a moral acceptance of the rule. In this way, Finnis claims
to have found a conceptual, logical link between validity and morality.
Neil MacCormick
shows that it is possible to incorporate non-rule standards into positivism. In
fact, he finds an element of circularity in Hart’s “rules of recognition”. The
“rules of recognition” pre-supposed judges. Existence of judges pre-supposes a
“rule of adjudication” (which is valid only in accordance with the “rules of
recognition”). In the Malaysian case of Sagong b. Tasi v The Selangor State
Government [2002] 2 MLJ 591, the court applied Australian Law on native Title
in its decision without “rules of recognition” of that law. Besides, Hart says
that in order for something to become a rule you need both the external and
internal aspect (the critical reflective attitude). McCormick claims that this
is not enough because the “critical reflective attitude” is a very subjective
thing which differs from one person to another. He also beliefs that there are
other factors to following laws, i.e. one’s understanding of it.
Ronald Dworkin
suggests that Hart’s philosophy cannot accommodate principles, and as a result,
are driven to rely on the notion of discretion. Dworkin also suggests that
judges do not make law. However, to Hart (in his open texture theory), judges
have discretion and that they sometimes engaged in law judicial making which is
evince in a number of cases like Donoghue v. Stevenson [1932] AC 562. On Hart’s
separation of law and morals, Dworkin claims that judges in applying the law
will also look at non standards i.e. morals values and principles of equity.
Hart provides no guidelines on judicial behaviour in the penumbra. Dworkin’s
prescriptions of ‘Hercules’ helps us to adopt a “constructive, morally charged”
view of the law. Hart gave no such guidelines because his exercise in
“descriptive sociology” was an exercise in descriptions, not prescriptions.
Also, Dworkin argues that rules are not enough. There is law beyond rules; that
principles, doctrines and standards are vital parts of the law and influence
judicial decisions in hard cases.
Hart did not
develop sociology of law or a significantly broadened conception of law. He
merely modernized and refined conceptions of jurisprudence inherited from
Bentham and Austin. English theory under him did not really integrate with
social theory. Jurisprudence in his hands remained largely expository,
analytical, apolitical and uncritical. This can be contrasted with Dworkin’s
approach that in interpreting the law, moral colours ought to be added to the
canvas.
Hart’s fidelity
to positivism showed up in his insistence on a formal criterion of validity
(the “rule/rules of recognition”). He refers his ignorance to answer any
question about the justification of the application of the coercive powers of
the state. He rejected the proposition that ideas of morality have a role to
play in identifying rules of law. Hart maintains that the Nazi-type legal
system (undeniably of moral wickedness), was law since the various features it
shares with other modern municipal legal system are too great for a
universal-descriptive legal theory to ignore. The system’s “rule or rules of
recognition” supply the authoritative and amoral test of validity. Hart’s
methodology concerned himself with legal facts and not moral values, with
descriptions and not prescriptions, with what is and not what ought to be.
Thus, Hart says that there is no logically necessary connection ‘between law
and coercion’ or ‘between law and morality’.
Nowadays, in
our society, there are numerous loopholes in our legal system that the
wrongdoers can always escape their liabilities. For example, the ‘pirated CDs
and VCDs’ problem. But, currently, there are no sufficient legislations to
prohibit the illegal activities effectively, and if we try to rely on
principles, we will discover another problem of principles. They are not
concrete or accurate enough for the judges to make an absolute decision.
Moreover, the society keeps moving every day and the development of science and
technology is fast beyond imagination. Therefore, rules can hardly keep
up-to-date with everything new and principles or moral standards may not be
applicable any more.
Hart’s theory
was general in that it was not tied to any particular legal system or legal
culture, but sought to give an explanatory and clarifying account of law as a
complex, social and political institution driven by a rich variety of rules.
His description of a legal system in terms of a union of primary and secondary
rules provides a tool of analysis for much that has puzzled both jurist and
political theorist even today. He has created the idea of law as a set of rules
instituting law as we know and it is today, and above all its criteria of
recognising valid law through the “rule/rules of recognition”.
Also, it should
be noted that, there are arguments supporting the accuracy of Hart’s view and
some others thought otherwise. At the end of the day, it cannot be denied that
Hart’s concepts of union of primary and secondary rules have been thought
provoking. No one else has offered a substitute which, with equal brevity, sets
out the crucial features of legal systems as Hart did. It may be that, there
are too complicated to be capable of interpretation in terms of a few concepts
without serious distortion. Perhaps, they are not the sort of entity of which
any model can be accurate one.
In conclusion,
as regard with Hart’s theory, it is agreed that there are loopholes in our
legal system, but the idea of judicial discretion is not really accurate.
Legislation should not be the job for the judges as we know that separation of
powers is an essential element of the rule of law. Thus, Hart’s theory is
arguably cannot be considered accurate, because it has its own strong and weak
points.
--------------------------------------------
Bibliography
- H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford University Press New York 2nd 1997);
- JG Riddall, Jurisprudence (Butterworths London 2nd 1999);
- L.B. Curzon, Q & A Series: Jurisprudence (Cavendish Publishing Limited London 3rd 2001);
- Mamari Stephens, “Maori Law and hart: A Brief Analysis”, available at www.upf.pf/IRIDIP/RJP/RJP7/18Stephens.doc, accessed on 23 February 2009;
- Mohammad Iftekhar Bin Salam, “Battle against HLA Hart, available at www.thedailystar.net/law/2006/05/04/opinion.htm, accessed on 23 February 2009;
- Norchaya Talib, Law of Torts in Malaysia (Sweet & Maxwell Asia 2nd 2003);
- Prof. Dr. Shad Saleem Faruqi’s Lecture Note on Jurisprudence;
- Prof. Hari Chand, Modern Jurisprudence (International Law Book Services Petaling Jaya 2005);
- Rowel Genn, Jurisprudence and Legal Theory (HLT Publications 1990);
- Wayne Morrison, Jurisprudence: From the Greeks to Post-Modernism (Cavendish Publishing Limited London 1997).
wah, sungguh murni sekali perkongsian ilmu ini..saya berharap awak akan dapat menerbitkan lebih banyak bahan bacaan berbentuk ilmiah seperti ini.
BalasPadamThat was a brilliant posting! Great sharing. Hope to see more law posting on your blog.
BalasPadamDespite the fact that each of the theory of law has its weaknesses, in your view, which model of theory is the "best thus far" ?
good article.
BalasPadamquestion; hart famously claimed that the concept of law is an exercise in sociological description. but has this really been true? he went onto enhance the issues with other theories. it was not mere description. i personally believe that he tried to bring his own definition of law. if you find my statement incorrect, could you please tell me what features of his theory support his claim?